Frame,
Object, and Vector
- The concept
of imagination is central to our understanding of both diegetic
music and the music we hear during the credits. Reference to imagination
also allows us to acknowledge important differences between them.
Ambiguity is possible and highly interesting, as when diegetic
music is employed as a substitute for the title theme proper.
However, the functions they fulfil are typically quite distinct:
while credits music prepares, coordinates or signals our engaging
in imagining, diegetic music is instead an object of that imagining.
Metaphorically, credits music is like a frame around a painting,
marking it off from the adjacent space, encouraging a certain
imaginative appreciation of it, and highlighting its status as
representation. Diegetic music, on the other hand, is more like
an element inside that very painting, just like the nose of a
face in a portrait, a piece of furniture in an interior, or a
bush in a landscape. The music played by an on-screen instrumentalist
is part of the soundscape of a scene in something like the way
the trees outside are part of its landscape.
- External,
or nondiegetic musicwhat most people intuitively
think of as film musicparticipates in both roles. It can
be both frame and object, sometimes simultaneously. Like credits
music, and like the muzak we incessantly hear in stores, bars,
shopping malls, it reminds us where we are and what we are
there for, especially when it plays profusely as in certain Hollywood
films of the 1930s and 1940s, for instance, or most contemporary
Hindi films. When this happens, nondiegetic music provides an
acoustical frame through (and not just before and after)
the film, thus bridging the gap between the beginning and end
credits.
- At the same
time, nondiegetic music may also point to elements inside the
story world.18
As many will recall, the sharks approach during the first
attack in Steven Spielbergs Jaws (1975) is conveyed
through the combined effect of a camera movement below sea level
and nondiegetic music in the soundtrack. This example is quite
typical, as nondiegetic musicunlike diegetic musicnever
points to itself as music but rather stands for
something else within the story world. The Jaws example
is also typical of what nondiegetic music most commonly stands
for: processes or events, both mental and physical
(like the approaching of an unseen character, the foreshadowing
of a future deed, a shift in a characters mood, the flashing
of an idea, etc.). Finally, the example is typical in that the
effect is achieved in collaboration with other components of the
film (in this case, a camera movement) and its success is contingent
on at least a minimal knowledge of the storys events and
circumstances.19
- This does
not exhaust our overview of the manifold roles played by nondiegetic
music. We still need to consider what we all sometimes superficially
refer to as setting the tone or the mood
of a scene. In these cases music acts like a vector: it
directs our attention toward a certain element or a particularly
meaningful aspect of a scene, guiding us to a certain understanding
and a certain emotional response to it.20
Nondiegetic music passes through our mind, as it were, before
we process the content of the images and the words of the characters,
filtering everything we see and hear, think and feel. We, the
spectators, adapt to the slant thereby produced just
as we naturally adapt to the point of view
suggested by the camera. This parallels the shaping of our attention
and emotional responses achieved through camera position and angle,
framing and composition, and, of course, acting.21
Nondiegetic music also contributes to indicating how the scene
relates to that which precedes and that which followsspatially,
temporally, and thematicallyintegrating what is done through
editing (sometimes reinforcing it, sometimes working against it).
We may refer to this as its syntactic function.
The Inaudible Orchestra
- As is the
case with diegetic music, the actual provenance of nondiegetic
music (the recording sessions, and the manipulation it undergoes
during a films production process) goes unnoticed during
a narrative film. The fact that this mass of potentially distracting
information rarely comes to our attention might seem a deliberate
attempt to efface cinemas sound technology. The actual source
of the music is effaced not only to the eyes but also
to the ears of the spectators. During a film the orchestra
may well be invisible or ghost-like (as in operatic practice since
Wagner). However, we might just as well say that it is inaudible
as an orchestra. Think of how film music is orchestrated
and recorded. Normally, the acoustics of the music are homogeneous
across an entire film. Volume is constant. Reverberation is usually
absent. Moreover, in many cases the orchestration is such that
no soloists or instrumental groups can be easily discerned. My
second rule [concerning the use of music], says director
François Truffaut, is to avoid instruments that are
too easy to identify or visualise, like the piano or the harp
(Chion 389). We may or may not disagree with Truffaut on this
point, but it is hard to deny that any combination of these features
is instrumental in diverting our attention from the performing
and recording aspects of the music heard.
-
A number of editing techniques also work to efface
the presence of the music. This is particularly true with respect
to the in- and out-points of the music cues (which are all but
noticeable in most conventional narrative films). I am thinking
of what is called sneaking in, the cueing in of music
at low volume underneath dialogue; or of the overlap,
i.e. the cutting of nondiegetic music during an overlap with
diegetic sound. These scoring practices are common not only
within Hollywood, but they also respond to needs and preferences
spread across many different filmmaking traditions. Bertoluccis
film, The Conformist(1970), for instance, features a
classic case of sound overlap right after the end of the credits.
As soon as the title theme ends, a new music cue abruptly takes
over. Its obsessive repetitiveness and extreme timbre point
effectively to the state of psychological breakdown suffered
by the protagonist. But the music also posed a problem: how
and when to make the cut, without calling attention to it? The
solution found was a most traditional overlap: the music stops
as a train of the Parisian métro enters the frame.
The train produces a loud noise and thus covers
the cut in the soundtrack.
- Hollywood
composers have openly referred to the use of devices such as the
overlap in terms of effacement.22
Efficacy of recording, compositional and editing practices notwithstanding,
the role of the spectator in minimizing the obtrusiveness of the
sound apparatus can hardly be underestimated. Representation demands
that attention to the technical apparatus and the network of efficient
causes giving rise to a sound be strongly attenuated. Interest
in representation, as a broadly anthropological fact, is an interest
in appearances to begin with, not in the physical or causal
processes giving rise to the stimuli that form the ground of those
appearances. It is in the spectators own interest that the
music heard during a film be translated as effectively and continuously
as possible into an incitement to imagine, or an attribute of
an imaginary world, or a filter better to understand and fully
respond to what happens in that world. This is a state of affairs
reminiscent of the economy of language comprehension. During a
conversation, language conveys semantic, affective, or pragmatic
content taking up the whole of our attention. As a result, attention
to speech as the product of a physiological apparatus or as a
string of mere phonemes is considerably reduced, as if continuously
deferred, despite the fact that the apparatus,
i.e. the speaker, may be sitting in front of her interlocutor.
- To the extent
that the most common composing and editing conventions enhance
continuous and single-minded participation in the narrative, then,
they reflect concerns as old as representation itself. However,
given the seemingly inexhaustible interest in representation across
cultures and the propensity for imaginary absorption into a narrative,
the question arises whether Hollywood filmmakers overestimated
the disruptive power that the visible or audible traces of their
work might have on the spectator.23
The degree of discretion and strategic placement of the music
cues is so much in excess of the minimal conditions for following
a narrative that it must be interpreted as a function of style
(and not as an inevitable development dictated by the nature of
human perception or cinematic representation). But why this style
and not others?
- Claudia
Gorbman has come close to an answer through a reference to the
alleged displeasure produced by ones awareness
of cinemas technological mediation. After discussing how
music wards off the displeasure of uncertain signification
by anchoring a potentially ambiguous image in meaning, Gorbman
goes on to say:
A second kind of displeasure that music helps to ward off is
the spectators potential recognition of the technological
basis of filmic articulation. Gaps, cuts,
the frame itself, silences in the soundtrackany reminders
of cinemas materiality which jeopardise the formation
of subjectivitythe process whereby the viewer identifies
as subject of filmic discourseare smoothed over, or spirited
away (recall Eisler and Adornos view of music as
magical antidote to the picture) by the carefully regulated
operations of film music. (58)
A summary of
subject positioning that Gorbman refers to and the debate
that has developed around it lies beyond the scope of this essay.24
Suffice it to say that with their emphasis on cuts, gaps, or the
frame as disruptive of the diegetic illusion subject
positioning, theorists givein my opiniontoo much
weight to the film as an already constituted object at the expense
of the film as reconstituted by the spectators mind. I hope
this crucial difference will emerge more clearly in the remainder
of my discussion.
- Gorbmans
passage would seem to contain an implicit answer to the question:
Why this style? For if one of the main functions of
film music is to smooth over cuts in the image track,
gaps, silences, the effect of the frame, and so on, then by the
same token music must also efface itself, as it were,
smoothing over its own cuts, gaps, and silences. Hence
the particular style of scoring we normally associate with mainstream
narrative cinema. It may well be true that producers self-consciously
effaced all traces of the recording, mixing, and playback process
for the sake of unity and cohesion. However, the question remains
whether their choice was dictated by what they deemed necessary
or, rather, by stylistic preferences. If we were to conclude that
the effect of widespread soundtrack practices is the impression
of unity, cohesion and absence of any technological mediation,
we would be implying that such practices are indeed necessary
to create this impression to begin with.
- A moments
reflection tells us that this is simply not the case. The spectator
can smooth over her viewing experience by restructuring
it mentally as more continuous and homogeneous than it appears
externally (either during the film or retrospectively, or both).
She can appreciate a representation as unitary and coherent even
when the apparatus is flaunted or even defective. After all, isnt
the frame of a painting fully visible without disturbing the one-ness
and coherence of what one is contemplating? The unity, coherence,
and smoothness of the contemplated object exist only
in the beholders imaginationif at alland are
as much the result of her skill, interest, and level of attention
as the external facets of the work. Correspondingly, a spectator
can form the impression of harmony and integration between music
and narrative under a variety of circumstances. When traces of
the recording process do survive in the finished product, she
can marginalize them. She can learn not to pay attention to them
through habituation, just as when playing an old record one increasingly
learns to ignore the sound of the scratches.
- By the same
token, ensuring that no attention be given to the performing apparatus
per se need not involve the apparatus being invisible
or absent. The existence of many theatrical traditions
in which little is done to efface the musicians or their instruments
proves that, pace Wagner, music can continuously and effectively
serve the need of representation even when a musical ensemble
is fully visible and the production process flaunted. Take opera
performance practices before Wagner. Or take Hou Hsiao-Hsiens
The Puppet Master again. True, the musicians are normally
behind the small wooden theatre, but they care little if someone
sees them out of the corner of her eye.25
- The use
of music in such forms of representation as theater, marionettes,
ballet, or opera is contingent on the idea that the spectator
will form the impression of at least some degree of cohesion and
mutual implication between music and the other components of the
work.26 This is
also true of many films whose scores differ markedly from the
scores of the so-called classical period of Hollywood cinema.
What is so peculiar to the latter is not the impression of cohesion
and absence of mediation they produce but, rather, the fact that
cohesion and absence of mediation are inscribed onto the soundtrack
itself before the spectator can produce them.
- What does
this entail? There is something greatly satisfying about the subtle,
carefully timed and highly functional scores of such films as
Otto Premingers Laura (1941), Billy Wilders
Sunset Boulevard (1950), or Alfred Hitchcocks Vertigo
(1958) (music by David Raksin, Franz Waxman, and Bernard Hermann,
respectively). Even less celebrated films display a complex interplay
of music and narrative and a rich array of effects. This is because
Hollywood scoring practices have resulted in a tradition
of matching music to images. Such devices as the overlap, the
sneaking in, or the use of a title theme marking the genre of
the filmto make three examplesare the expression of
this tradition and contribute to a language of their
own as rich as any other.
- On the other
hand, they also represent a style whose goal seems to reduce to
a minimum the cooperation of the audience, as if the spectator
had to be spoon-fed, so to speak, in order to weld
music to narrative. To be sure, the obsessive need to efface the
in- and out-points of the music cues eventually became (and still
is) a sign of compliance with a crystallized style. However, it
must have originated from the fear that the spectator might be
incapable of transcending his awareness of the material processes
at work in making the representation possible. In less fastidiously
constructed forms of spectacle, the spectators relative
lack of attention to the production process is also the result
of the intensity of his imaginary involvement with what is being
represented, not only the facets of the work or the circumstances
of reception themselves. Focus on the represented content as well
as its foil, momentary disregard for the apparatus, emerge out
of negotiations and adjustments taking place between the spectator
and the work (or performance). Habituation sometimes makes these
adjustments unnecessary.
- Not so in
Hollywood mainstream cinema: instead of relying solely on the
audiences capacity to concentrate on the narrative, Hollywood
filmmakers have deemed it necessary to cleanse their soundtracks
systematically of any signs of intervention. By the same token,
experimentation is discouraged, lest the spectator be distracted.
This implies the simplistic idea that the material facets of the
text alone are responsible for the cohesion and unity between
music and narrative experienced by the spectator, irrespective
of his capacity to construct that cohesion through imagining.
Inscribed in many a Hollywood score is the derogatory view of
an unimaginative, inattentive, listening subject, easily distracted
by either the apparatus or any deviation from the norm, or both.
Anxiety over unity and cohesion, then, is not a function of representation
tout court. Rather, it is a function of a certain view
of the listening experience at the cinema and, indirectly, the
spectators mind.
|
|