Humanly
Organized Sounds
- Strictly
speaking, music is not needed to ease the spectators immersion
into the world of the story. A large number of music-less opening
credits testifies to this. In fact, there are cases in which the
absence of music is necessary to the success and stylistic coherence
of a film. In Woody Allens Zelig (1983), for instance,
the
silence accompanying the brief credits sequence conveniently
underscores the fact that the film is a mock documentary. Music
is also conspicuously absent from the beginning credits in all
of Luis Buñuels later filmsfrom Belle de
Jour (1966) to his last work, That Obscure Object of Desire
(1977). Far from being merely a capricious rejection of a movie
convention, the lack of music in the credits foreshadows the character
of the soundtrack as a whole. It is the correlative of the de-dramatized
plot and subdued light, colors, and sounds of a world in which
the ordinary and the surreal miraculously meet. In a gesture more
radical still, Federico Fellini disposes of the credits altogetherexcept
for the brief display of the titleat the beginning of his
metacinematic film
8 1/2
(1963). In this case, the choice is also highly symptomatic of
the film as a whole. In the moment normally allotted for the credits,
Fellini reflects the absolute coincidence between the film the
protagonist Guido is planning to make and the film were
watching.
- These
examples notwithstandingand there are many othersthe
use of music over the beginning credits of a film is an overwhelmingly
widespread phenomenon. Indeed, it has become a norm that very
few films violate, and when this happens, as I have shown, that
in itself is perceived as a marked, highly significant authorial
gesture fulfillinga highly specialised function. Why? Though it
may not facilitate our immersion in the fiction as directly and
vividly as in the Another Woman example examined above,
music invariably prepares, enables, and signifies the perceptual,
cognitive, affective shift that marks the spectators psychic
life the moment a film begins. It is like a passport into
the world of the film, and on the other end it becomes a signpost
pointing to our exit. The conventionalization of the practice
has made the presence of the music necessary even though the effects
that motivated its employment to begin with may be overlooked
(or, better, overheard). At least, hearing music reassures
us that a convention is being honored: it plays because one expects
to hear it, and is thus necessary to the extent that it is part
of the decorum of the spectacle. We might call this
the zero degree of film musics effects on the
spectator.6
- If music
signifies a nascent relationship between the film and the spectator,
then it must be perceived and employed as humanly organized
sound (to use John Blackings expression). This is
to say that upon acting on the listener, film music must mobilize
the same mental resources, behavioural patterns, social and cultural
conditioning involved in the reception of other kinds of cultural
artifacts. Unquestionably one of the main components
of the beginning of the spectacle, music does not directly provoke
a state of mind appropriate to the appreciation of a film, like
a mere physical agent acting on a passive physiological apparatus.
Rather, music socializes the emotional and cognitive shift
the spectator undergoes in preparing herself for a cinematic narrative.
It is a socially constructed mediator, not a material cause in
the strict sense.7
- Enabler,
conventional sign, and invitation to imagine: the significance
of this cluster of overlapping functions cannot be underestimated.
Not only are these functions the surviving traces of ancient rituals,
they also constitute the necessary stepping-stone, both historically
and psychologically, for the successful deployment of a whole
array of syntactic, expressive, narrative, and symbolic functions
within the ensuing narrative. The music played over the beginning
credits, in other words, underscores the shift toward the imaginative
understanding of not only images and sounds, but also of music
itself.
The Ontology of Diegetic Music: Hearing as
Double Intentionality
- The music
we hear during a movie comes from the loudspeakers
in the theater and is the result of a number of stages: recording,
editing, mixing, and playback. One hardly pays any attention to
this, as the soundtrack is normally perceived in terms of a source
internal to the scene depicted (be it a radio, a voice, or a musical
instrument). This anchorage to a source is sometimes called diegeticization,
and scholars often call this music diegetic music
(from the word diegesis, which in film studies parlance
has come to mean story world or fictional world).8
- Despite
the fact that during a film we never quite abandon
the belief that the music were hearing has been recorded
and subsequently manipulated, it is undeniable that anchoring
music to a diegetic source lowers our moment-to-moment awareness
of the production process as well as our awareness of the actual
source of emission (the loudspeakers). In this respect, diegetic
music functions in the same way as the objects, places, people
who populate the movie world. They too monopolize
our attention, diverting it from the fact that we are seeing a
photographic image.9
- The spectator
is co-responsible for this process. When we hear music in a film
as if it were produced by a band playing on-screen, we are abstracting
from any considerations about the actual genesis of the sound
and its subsequent manipulation during the filmmaking process.
We are concentrating instead of what the sound is a sound of,
in the context of the story world. This process of perceptual
abstraction may have become a habit, but it isnt imposed
upon a passive, defenceless, perceiving subject.
It is an act of selection, memory, and ultimately construction,
and it is central to the appreciation of many forms of representation,
such as the spoken theatre, ballet, or painting. Upon pondering
the mysterious way in which shapes and marks can be made
to signify and suggest other things beyond themselves, art
historian E. H. Gombrich has famously named this process illusion.
Illusion is a charged word, however, fraught with implications
of error, deception, and even hallucination.10
Let us refer to this process instead as imagining.
- It may seem
strange to invoke the concept of imagination to explain the perception
of diegetic music. What, one may wonder, is there to imagine?
Isnt the music out there, audible to anyone
in the movie theatre? To be sure, hearing diegetic music at the
cinema need not consist in the inner, mental recreation of the
sonic manifestation of the music as such, for music is played
aloud and is rendered with a high degree of resolution by the
recording technology. When I use the word imagining, however,
I am not referring to the notion of imagination as a kind of daydreaming,
the conjuring up of mental imagery about things absent, or the
mental, inwardly completion of things barely sketched as in the
everyday usage of the word. Rather, I am using the word imagination
as the ability to consider things that are not taken to be real
(whether absent or not).
- In terms
of this definition of imagination, to take Laurence Olivier acting
Hamlet on stage, for instance, is toimagine that he is
Hamlet.
Note that in imagining that he is Hamlet we are not forming a
mental image of Hamlet; rather, we are taking Olivier himself,
the actor in flesh and blood whom we see and hear on stage, to
be Hamlet. Similarly, upon looking at a trompe loeil
painting of a fruit basket, we are imagining that we are seeing
a fruit basket. No inwardly completion of the
visual object is necessary, since the painting is replete with
information, spelling everything out to the smallest detail and
in the most realistic fashion possible. Still, looking at such
a painting is to engage in imagining to the extent that looking
at what it depicts is simultaneous with the awareness that we
are looking at a painting. In this respect, there is continuity
between a trompe loeil and the most barely sketched
outline calling for much projection on the part of the beholder.
They are both props in a game of make-believe.11
- So it is
with a cinematic scene, and the music we hear in it (if any).
Hearing the music coming from an on-screen radio in a film is
an act of imagination to the extent that we are hearing the music
as if it itself were radio music within the movie world, exploring
it perceptually as if it were such, and responding to it accordingly.
Of course, this also implies that we imaginatively attribute the
musics source to the radio we see or know to be in the scene,
despite knowing full well that the music actually
comes from a recorded track and reaches our ears via a set of
loudspeakers. Imagining consists precisely of the capacity to
regard the recorded sound as the result of a chain of virtual
relations internal to the story world. We need not think of this
as an inner, occult mental activity. It can be described, more
simply, as a form of behavior.12
- Imagining
is to take an interest in appearances, while maintaining intact
ones awareness of the status of the physical substrata that
make those very appearances possiblebe they actors, pictures,
printed words, moving images, or recorded sounds. The simultaneity
of these seemingly contradictory stances is a
puzzling phenomenon, difficult to express in words (see the epigraph
by Ruskin above). Philosopher Roger Scruton has characterized
this phenomenon as an instance of double intentionality. Upon
looking at a picture of a face, says Scruton, I am presented
with two simultaneous objects of perception: the real picture,
and the imaginary face (87).13
Approaching the question as an experimental psychologist, J.J.
Gibson too has formulated the problem in terms of a duality: The
picture is both a scene and a surface, and the scene is paradoxically
behind the surface. This duality of information is the
reason the observer is never quite sure how to answer the question,
What do you see? (280).
- The contrastive
pair of nouns scene/surface is not of much help in
describing the perception of a diegetic soundtrack, not even metaphorically.
But the notion of a dual experience is. Like a face in a picture,
diegetic music is the object of twofold perception. The spectator
is confronted with a real soundthe recorded sound of the
music via the loudspeakersas well as a virtual onethe
music as the imaginary product of agents and causes internal to
the movie world. An immense, unbridgeable gulf
separates them, both ontologically and psychologically. It is
because they are so incommensurable that the real and the virtual
(or imaginary) sound do not exclude each other in our perception.
They act upon two different areas of the psyche. They occupy adjacent
yet distinct spaces. That is why one actually hears both.14
- Dual perception
is paralleled by dual belief. Note that there is no contradiction
between believing the music to be a (virtual) element in the diegesis
and believing it to be a (real) sound in a (real) space. Indeed,
there cannot be any contradiction between these two beliefs,
since they reflect two entirely distinct ways of approaching musical
sound. They are mutually exclusive only in the sense that ones
attention can focus on only one at a time.
- No matter
how much we may be caught up in a story, our belief
that the music consists of pre-recorded sound emanating via the
loudspeakers is never called into question. The belief in diegetic
musics actual absence and impossibility at the moment of
its apparent presence or realityto paraphrase Ruskinpermeates
the whole listening experience. True, such belief may not be entertained
or asserted on a moment-by-moment basis. Even then, however, it
will be present, alive, even nurtured. This is because of the
peculiar nature of belief as a mental state. A
belief is not so much an occurrent mental act as a disposition
or readiness to act in a certain manner. As such, a belief remains
alive across time independent of whether one consciously
focuses on its content or provides external, behavioral evidence
that one believes. It follows that to hold certain beliefs about
the actual physical status of music need not entail entertaining
them on a moment-to-moment basis, let alone articulating them
in language.15
- Just as
our knowledge of the actual nature and provenance of film music
is never quite discarded, so is disbelief about its
fictionality never suspended, to quote Coleridges
notorious expression. During a film, in short,
beliefs concerning the actual status of the music heard are neither
discarded nor suspended. They are, more simply, nonoccurrent.
The perception of diegetic music differs from an illusion proper
because it does not entail that we discard our beliefs about the
actual status of the sound in the physical world we inhabit.16
- That said,
these beliefs make themselves felt. But how? As a readiness to
differentiate a failure of the power system from a silence in
the make-believe world of the story, for example; or as a kind
of safety blanket enclosing the film-goers listening experience.
The firm conviction that diegetic music exists in a purely fictional
realm frees the filmgoer, as it were, enhancing her
sensitivity to its dramaturgical and poetic roles. In this respect,
the reception of diegetic music merely mirrors the reception of
representation in general. The firmness of
the spectators belief in the fictional status of the narrative,
makes her more vulnerable to a range of responses that are not
as readily available when we observe human dramas being played
out in our real world.17
There is a sense, then, in which the intensity, richness, and
vivacity of our absorption into a world of make-believe is evidence
not of a deceptive, illusory state of mind but rather of the oppositean
all too encompassing understanding of the nature of representation
and the subjects relation to it.
|
|